WAS ZORAN DJINDJIC AN
IMMORALIST?
By Vesna Pešic
I deliberately used the term immoralist in the headline. I had in mind
Andre Gide's work under the same title dealing with immorality. Gide's hero, as I
understood it, was neither amoral nor unmoral, not a person violating moral norms and
hurting other people. He was a person guided by aesthetic values focused on exhibitionist
smashing of the rule that shape people's behavior. Or more precisely, the Immoralist
researches the field of absolute freedom. Gide does the same in his other books such as
"Prometheus Misbound" or "The Vatican Cellars." One of his heroes
slaps a passerby and gives him an envelope with money. That's how Gide testes free will,
unbound and motivated solely by pure negation of the rules channeling our behavior - from
decency to morality.
I am using Gide and his immorality as a space of smashed moral norms and
absolute freedom to pose a crucial question: "Did Zoran Djindjic with his famous
phrase 'If you are concerned with morals, go to church' advocated immorality in the sense
of absolute freedom?" Was he using the phrase to advocate something worse than
aesthetic exhibitionism taking that politics was immoral by the nature of things? Does it
mean that politicians are allowed immorality? Does it mean that a politician concerned
with morals should better withdraw from politics and turn to the church?
It would make no sense to focus on one of Zoran Djindjic's slogans had
this particular one not caused an avalanche of criticism and negative comments claiming,
as one, that Djindjic advocates incompatibility of morals and politics. Not only laymen
interpreted the phrase as a green light to immorality in politics but also some
philosophers took that his statement could only be understood as political immorality. Of
course, the same as ordinary people, philosophers may feel animosity towards some
political party or politician. But, unlike ordinary people, they cover up their animosity
with philosophical apparatus that seems neutral and "objective" to readers.
Their interpretations are the more so dangerous since they hush up the interpreted
subject. Therefore, the interpreted subject should firstly be given chance to present
himself in his "subjectivity" and only then expound his analysis. This is what I
have to do. I must admit that I've like Zoran Djindjic as a politician. Readers will draw
their own conclusions whether or not my interpretation of Djindjic's famous phrase about
morals and church is a product of my affection or a valid argumentation.
Well, I will try to prove that "morals in the church" has
nothing to do with immorality in politics or with Zoran Djindjic's "immoral
personality." Even should we assume that he was such a person the very phrase would
give no hint in that direction. Indeed, what was it that Zoran Djindjic had in mind? To
answer the question I firstly have to determine the context in which the phrase was
uttered and from which it derives. The context of the phrase is Zoran Djindjic's political
philosophy centered on differentiating the area "of politics" from others
fields, morals included.
Djindjic's philosophy centers on the sustainability of a modern state:
on what makes its foundations, what constitutes it and makes it possible. Only once we
understand this we shall understand why was it that he separated morals and politics into
two different areas of activity. Zoran was primarily preoccupied with understanding the
disintegration of pre-modern society into society and state, as a constitutive
precondition of both phenomena - a modern society and a modern state. Before the split
"political" was not differentiated as a separate field of activity, as a sui
generis area, as an area that can be defined without invoking the God (religion), virtue
(morals) or some natural order (nature). In his study "Community, Nature, Civil War:
Hobbes and Marx" Djindjic thoroughly analyzes the "U-turn" in the notion of
political. I will, therefore, rely on that study to present my argumentation.
In his study Djindjic notes that notions of political become slippery
when treated in their historical meanings. He is interested in "the last layers of
the notion of political, accumulated in the new era." Since this is about the 20th
century notion of political, the concept could be called a "Hobbes paradigm."
This paradigm will show that the notion possesses criteria of its own, designating a
relatively independent activity when compared with other activities such as morals,
aesthetics, religion and economy. So, what's the "ultimate differentiation" of
political to which any such basic activity boils down? It obviously boils down to morals,
to the difference between right and wrong, to an aesthetic criterion of nice and ugly, or
to economic criteria of useful (profitable) and useless. Zoran Djindjic takes a specific
mode of integration for a compass needle differentiating the political from all other
contents and areas. Understanding this implies understanding of the preconditions of a
community for getting integrated that way.
What community is integrated by "political?" What are the
preconditions of a political community and why is it that those preconditions direct us
towards their content-free foundation (which is not the case with morals) and suggest that
"the reality of a political community rests on reflection and that generality is its
way of existence?" It suffices to say that political integration is necessitated only
by those communities that have lost their natural homogeneity, i.e. the communities that
have been pluralized for good. And this is not about any pluralism but the pluralism of
convictions. Convictions can be integrated within a content-free frame only, the political
frame the catalogue of notions of which has wiped off morals, religion, aesthetics,
nature, etc. To understand this we have to go step by step back to Hobbes' paradigm.
Hobbes differentiates natural state characterized by "the right of
every individual to everything," i.e. by absence of law. Opposite to it is the civil
order (status civilis). His theory recognizes an unbound individual guided by uncontrolled
passions and aggressive egoism, which he describes as "war of all against all."
The important thing in his hypothesis is that individuals are unbound but that means not
that the natural state can be described as a state of open possibilities that "counts
not on some teleology in the background." Hobbes takes that this pluralism of needs
(passions) can be pacified in the natural state if all actors opt for maintenance of life
and give up the sovereignty of their needs. He fixes this denial in "social
contract" as a demarcation line between the natural state and normative order.
And what is the basis of the normative order? Hobbes takes that an order
is established when individuals wield their sovereignty to the state (Leviathan). However,
Djindjic warns that conflict of passions (aspiration of many individuals for naturally
limited objects) and renouncement of conflicts are not enough as preconditions for
establishment of an order. Passions are not something objective but subject to
interpretation. In the situation of pluralization (freedom) an order does not derive from
suppression of freedoms and selfish interests but from pacification of pluralized
convictions - those conflicts are irreconcilable since they all aspire to general
applicability. Religious wars, says Zoran, testified that maintenance of life was not the
fundamental value for individuals but victory of one's beliefs. Hobbes is wrong, says
Zoran, when he assumes that the interest in life would overcome beliefs, since wars have
been wagged for beliefs. There would be no problem whatsoever had the life had the upper
hand. How was it possible then to overcome religious wars, i.e. conflicts of beliefs, each
of which has aspired to general applicability?
Djindjic makes the following point: the conflict in the civil war was
not a struggle for survival but a result of disintegration of the Christian normative
universalism. Such a conflict (of pluralized beliefs) was surmountable in the political
community that "did not stand for any order but for the order incorporating two basic
presuppositions: aspirations for general applicability reached unbearable intensity and
'the sides at war' were ready to give them up." But this is not about "resigned
disavowal of one's beliefs," this is about an order that is possible only if all give
up general applicability of their beliefs and adopt a changed, though intense, attitude
towards it so that they all can control one another and thus prevent any aspiration for
general applicability from being recognized. Consequently, this means separation of
private and public. Passions, interests and beliefs are moved to the private sphere
(society) whereas public, i.e. political, is constituted as content-free, a frame of
integration of the society that is as general as possible. And that can only be law
applicable to all.
In conclusion, the political - enabling a performance of various
interests - constitutes law (Constitution) rather than morals. Politics has separated from
morals because morals do not make a constituent part of the foundation on which politics
rests. It is law - rather than morals - that secures a political community and a modern
state. Of course, this means not that politicians are unaccountable to moral judgment and
that politics should be amoral. The point is that politics constitutes law rather than
morals. Zoran Djindjic said many times that morals is important for people - and that is
indisputable the same as that integration of a modern society, its management and
regulation of social relations do not rest on the criteria of right and wrong but on law.
Only law secures free expression of interests and different beliefs. Zoran Djindjic has
never negated moral values. But, for him, setting foundations for modern politics and
state is another story. "Morals in the church" advertises not immorality in
politics or personal immorality - it only claims that political processes and struggles
are, as a separate domain, constituted and regulated by law rather than by morals. |